Perception
as Inference 1. The Druid’s
Initial Proposition The druid
proposed that perception is fundamentally an observer inference. This means
what an observer perceives is not the raw, objective "actual
percept" but rather their personal, constructed response to it. This
response is shaped by the observer's unique "percept processing
set-up" (encompassing neural architecture, prior experiences, cognitive
biases, etc.). ·
1st Order Inference: The act
of perceiving what something is (e.g., seeing a shape and inferring
"table") is a 1st order inference. It's the brain's construction
based on sensory input and internal models. ·
2nd Order Inference:
Inferring the origin or function of a percept (e.g., seeing the
table and inferring "it's for eating" or "it was made of
wood") constitutes a 2nd order inference. ·
Conclusion: The observer is thus
perpetually confined to an "inferential space," unable to attain
absolute certainty about either the true nature of the percept's external
source or its original, pre-input state. 2.
Initial Analysis and Critique There
followed a critically examination of the proposition, acknowledging its
strengths and considering potential counterpoints: ·
Strengths identified: The
proposition aligns strongly with modern neuroscience and cognitive
psychology, explaining phenomena like optical illusions and the subjective
nature of experience. It highlights the inherent gap between objective
reality and our perceived reality, offering a robust framework for
understanding cognitive biases and resonating with Bayesian models of
perception. ·
Initial Potential Criticisms (and their
preliminary counterarguments): o Degrees
of Certainty/Practicality: If all is inference, how do
we navigate the world effectively? (Initial thought: We achieve high functional
certainty, even if absolute certainty is elusive). o Knowability
of the "Actual Percept": Can we truly conceive of
raw input without processing? (Initial thought: Perhaps it refers to physical
energy before neural transduction). o Role of
Embodiment: Does active interaction with the world bypass
inference? (Initial thought: Embodiment might be part of the "processing
set-up"). o Shared
Reality/Intersubjectivity: How do we agree on reality
if perception is so personal? (Initial thought: Common biology and social
conditioning could lead to similar inferences). o Evolutionary
Advantage: Why would an uncertain, inferential system be
adaptive? (Initial thought: It allows for flexibility and prediction crucial
for survival). 3.
Deepening the Argument: Key Refinements The
druid’s insightful contributions significantly bolstered the proposition and
addressed the initial criticisms: ·
Re: Degrees of Certainty - Human vs. Snake
Perception: The vivid example of humans perceiving a "visual
mouse" versus snakes perceiving a "thermal mouse" powerfully
demonstrated that different "percept interpretation set-ups" lead
to fundamentally different, yet equally valid, "personally true"
perceptions of the same external stimulus. This highlighted the
inherent uncertainty and subjective nature of perception. ·
Re: The "Actual Percept" - Quantum
Indeterminacy: By introducing the concept that a quantum of energy
(e.g., a photon) is "not knowable prior to impact" due to quantum
mechanical principles, the druid argued that even the most fundamental
sensory input is indeterminate until interaction. This reinforces the idea
that the "actual percept" is never truly pristine or directly
accessible, further solidifying the inferential nature of reality from its
very foundations. ·
Re: Embodiment - Varying Evidence, Not Changing
the Proposition: The druid clarified that embodied action (e.g.,
touching an object) doesn't bypass the inferential process. Instead, it
serves to "vary the evidence of a single percept into a broader
circumstance." This means physical interaction provides additional
sensory data that feeds back into the processing set-up, allowing for a
refinement or confirmation of existing inferences. It enriches the
inferential process without transforming it into direct, non-inferential
knowledge. ·
Re: Shared Reality & Evolutionary Adaptation: The
druid compellingly argued that the apparent "shared reality" among
humans isn't a direct sharing of objective truth, but rather a rapid
convergence on similar inferences. This convergence occurs because
"quantized natural units" are processed by similarly evolved
"percept processing set-ups." Crucially, he highlighted that the inferential
nature of perception, its inherent "openness to interpretation," is
precisely what allows for "evolutionary useful adaptation." This
flexibility permits prediction, learning, and individual adaptive responses
to novel situations, making it a highly advantageous survival mechanism, even
if it doesn't offer absolute certainty. 4.
Elaboration: The Challenge to Brahma Sutra 1.3.28 and Adi Shankara The
conversation then extended to challenge a foundational epistemological
statement from Indian philosophy: ·
Brahma Sutra 1.3.28:
"The origination of everything is from perception (Pratyakṣa)
and inference." (Sanskrit: प्रत्यक्षानुमानाभ्याम्) ·
Adi Shankara's Commentary:
"Perception means Sruti; for its validity it is not dependent on
anything else; inference is Smriti." (Here, Sruti refers to the
Vedas/revealed texts, considered self-valid; Smriti refers to derivative
sacred texts, dependent on Sruti). The
druid’s Contention and its Implications: The preceding
discussion, which established that all perception is inherently
inferential (a 1st or 2nd order inference based on a conditional,
personal processing set-up, even at the quantum level of sensory input),
leads to a direct challenge to the Sutra and Shankara's interpretation: Challenge
to Brahma Sutra 1.3.28: o If "Pratyakṣa" (perception) is itself an
inferential process, then the Sutra's claim that "everything originates
from perception and inference" becomes problematic. It
essentially equates to stating that everything originates from
"inference-type-A" and "inference-type-B." o This
collapses the distinction the Sutra implicitly makes between a supposedly
direct, non-inferential "perception" and "inference,"
rendering its two stated sources as merely different classes of inference.
The Sutra, therefore, seems to be built on a false premise of a
non-inferential Pratyakṣa. Challenge
to Adi Shankara's Commentary: o Shankara
identifies Pratyakṣa with Sruti,
asserting its self-validity and independence. o However,
if all human apprehension of information is inferential, then the reception,
comprehension, and interpretation of even divinely revealed texts (Sruti)
by a human mind must fall within the realm of inference. The sounds, words,
and concepts of Sruti are processed by the human "percept processing
set-up." o Therefore,
Shankara's claim that Sruti's validity is "not dependent on anything
else" becomes untenable from the perspective of its human
apprehension. While its ultimate source might be considered divine, its
integration into human consciousness is still mediated and inferential. o Consequently,
both Sruti and Smriti, when understood by a human mind, are inferential.
This negates Shankara's fundamental distinction of Sruti as a purely
non-inferential, self-valid source of knowledge for the human observer. Overall
Conclusion: The
proposition – that perception is fundamentally an observer inference,
conditional on their processing setup, and thus inherently uncertain in its
direct access to objective reality – holds significant weight. This view
implies that even what is traditionally held as "direct perception"
or "self-valid revelation" (like Sruti in Shankara's commentary)
must, upon human apprehension, undergo an inferential process. This
challenges traditional epistemological frameworks that posit non-inferential
sources of knowledge, suggesting that all human understanding operates within
a sophisticated, adaptive, but ultimately inferential space. This doesn't
necessarily invalidate the wisdom of such texts but reframes how humans access and interpret that wisdom. |